Rousseau
Closer to Marx Than to Locke
David Bozarth
Sonoma State University
POLS 315
15 June 2004
“Were there such a thing as a nation of Gods, it would be a democracy. So perfect a form of government is not suited to mere men.” [1]
Karl Marx might have been
reluctant to accept characterization of Rousseau as transitional between Locke
and himself. Locke was a dead-on-the-money political theorist; Marx was a
critical-visionary economic and social analyst. Both were concerned with the
matter and forces of human affairs.
Rousseau’s Social Contract
is a thorough and meaningful reflection on a brilliant hallucination. There is
no such “general will” among any substantial body of humans, but the engaging
idealism of Rousseau convinces us that function follows form in the life of the
body politic. Marx the “scientific” observer would have now to agree that
Rousseau carried Locke’s groundwork aloft on mythic wings and returned in
searing glory, bearing the fire of totalitarian utopia.
FREEDOM & SLAVERY
Freedom is a prime essential
quality of the state of nature. In forming a social pact, humans accept
limitation on individual freedom, in order to gain collective freedom from
danger. Locke examines this process, emphasizing the individual’s stake in the
association. Rousseau is similarly concerned with formation principles, but
requires the forming associates to check their individualism at the door
(p186), to enable expression of the general will. Marx sees the triumph of
bourgeois society, essential in redirecting the systematic exploitation endemic
to corrupt individualism, as preparation for a truly reformed contract founded
on community. Rousseau may be seen to share Marx’s interest in suppressing
anti-communitarian conceits of the individual, but Rousseau expresses (within Social
Contract) less regard for the flourishing of the individual within a
rational society (Marx). This suggests, as might be expected over the course of
a century, a more refined consideration by Marx compared with Rousseau’s
earlier reaction to the “conservative liberalism of the Enlightenment.”
Locke and Rousseau agree that
it is no person’s natural right to submit to slavery. Locke appeals to a
seemingly specious ontological or theological proposition (one doesn’t own
one’s own life to give)(p15). Rousseau claims that surrender of freedom is an
irrational contravention of one’s own nature (p175). None has right over the
freedom of others, including offspring (pp174). Furthermore, if one can submit,
then by logical extension an entire population can submit themselves – an
insult to reason (p173).
Locke allows enslavement in
case of a just conquest, as continuation of the state of war, and asserts that
by consent, such a relationship is transformed out of slavery into something
more palatable (p16). Rousseau refutes
this specifically and at length. Might is not right, and “war … is something
that occurs not between man and man, but between States … a State can have as
its enemies only other States, not men at all.” But “slavery” takes on a more
encompassing meaning for Rousseau. Life under despotism is slavery, and
guarantees the sword, not peace for those who submit (pp173-178).
For Marx, slavery (class
exploitation) is the dominant paradigm. The masters, moreover, are themselves
enslaved to the extent that they must propagate their ownership or suffer
retraction. Only by slave revolt and seizure of political and economic control,
can liberation be achieved for all.
In Locke, freedom for the
individual is achieved through social contract and effective government. In
Rousseau, freedom for the population is achieved through submission to the
general will, which is based on social contract and nurtured by effective
government. In Marx, freedom for every
population (and thus for each person) is to be achieved through economic and
social restructuring – and once a critical mass of freedom exists on the
planet, the State will wither away.
PROPERTY & LABOR
Private property is a
fundamental right of the Lockean individual. Most relations among persons, the
social contract, and governmental structures are all organized around
protection of private value interests.
Rousseau performs one of many
virtuous mental transformations, as humans associate to form a compact. All
their holdings of material value (including land) instantaneously accrue to the
commonwealth. In the same instant, all those items that were obtained or
occupied in moderation, through honest means, are returned and assigned to the
original owners, occupants, tenants, farmers, miners, artisans, and so on.
(Presumably, the original chain of custody applies instantly as well, so that
basically everyone gets their stuff back.) Anything in excess of what is needed
by a person, according to the general will, is retained by the commonwealth. Likewise,
all future acquisitions and transactions are subject to the limitation of
prudence established by the general will.
In essence, this material
abundance held in common coincides closely with formation of the State, to be
distinguished from the Sovereign (the People guided by the general will). Also,
Rousseau’s notion of fair sharing coupled with right of first occupancy, is
based on a deeper concern with equality:
Under a bad government such equality is but apparent and illusory. It serves only to keep the poor man confined within the limits of his poverty, and to maintain the rich in their usurpation. In fact, laws are always beneficial to the ‘haves’ and injurious to the ‘have-nots.’ Whence it follows that life in a social community can thrive only when all its citizens have something, and none have too much (p189).
Marx sees the holding and
pursuit of “class property” (property gained and held by means or for purpose
of class exploitation by the bourgeoisie) as target for abolition by socialist
reform[2].
Redistribution of wealth and real property are to be mechanisms for alleviating
the inequities engendered by class exploitation, and for providing an economic
basis for the well-being and productivity of an egalitarian society.
Locke, Rousseau, and Marx all
hold that material goods acquire value from the labor of people, and that labor
entitles the worker to some benefit from the work. Rousseau agrees with Locke
that individuals have a right to hold and exploit private property, but insists
(like Marx) that the commonwealth retain a more fundamental order of ownership
over all valuable resources in its domain, even to the extent of
redistribution.
POWER & GOVERNMENT
Once an association has been
formed by social contract in the Lockean world, the next thing to watch out for
is tyranny. He separates a proper
government into Legislative, Executive, and Federative sections, each with
defined and limited powers, in order to hold back the heavy hand of government
and protect the rights of property owners.
Rousseau is more concerned
with the corrupting tendencies of individual ambition. This is consistent with
the character of his political theory as outlined in Social Contract -
complex in its interdependency, and replete with reliance on metaphysical
gymnastics. One example from the text:
The difficulty is to understand how it is possible to have an act of government before ever a government exists, and how a People, which can only be sovereign or subject, can, in certain circumstances, become prince or magistrate.
It is here that there again comes to light one of those
astonishing properties of the body politic by which it reconciles apparently
contradictory operations. For this situation is brought about by a sudden
conversion of sovereignty into a democracy, in such a sort that, without any
noticeable change, and merely as a result of a new relation of all to all, the
citizens, having become magistrates, pass from general acts to particular acts,
from the law to the execution of law.(p265)
Rousseau at once proceeds to
offer a concrete example. His reasoning is coherent. My claim is that his
theory is riddled with dependencies on such formal convolutions, and is
therefore brittle. This is significant because perturbations happen in the life
of the body politic – individuals plot, they are greedy, and so on. A
circumspect genius, Rousseau does well in vigilance for the integrity of his
system of thought and his prescriptions for government. His bulwark of
protection for the Sovereign and the State is built on derogation of individual
rights and the submission of the individual to the general will.
Both Locke and Rousseau
advocated expression of the popular will by government, separation of powers,
and limited Executive prerogative. Locke avoided abstractions like the
Sovereign and the general will, in part because his theory of government was
less ambitious, but also because he took for granted the greedy self-interest
feared by Rousseau, and found less cause for alarm.
Locke, Rousseau, and Marx
spanned over two centuries between them. They all attempted to explain how
things came to be the way they are, in political society. They each critiqued
existing power structures and offered prescriptions for change. Marx had less
to say about the structure of a continuing government, because his long-range
view entailed obsolescence of the State.
Rousseau and Locke are
associated with classical liberal tradition: Locke on the short list of
godfathers, Rousseau off-sprung and heading elsewhere. For Marx, classical
liberalism and bourgeois society breathed the same air and were busy fulfilling
the same destiny together.
Rousseau was not explicitly
utopian or totalitarian. Nominally, his task was to apply the lessons of
history and reason to the problem of a lasting national government in a
changing but seemingly well-understood world. His detailed historical
methodology, his strong communitarian emphasis, and his rationalist framework
may have given Karl Marx food for thought.
Rousseau envisioned a
Sovereign people of like mind on key issues, with similarly directed urges for
cohesion and justice, so that deviants would be identified and processed so to
avoid harming the Sovereign, and the mechanism of society could run
uninterrupted. While in harmony with Puritan values, this is more than a
stone’s throw from the Lockean political world of expected conflict and
compromise amid institutions designed to govern least.
The hope of forcing some
variant of freedom through sublimation of the individual in the Sovereign is a
vision with attraction. Like it or not, it’s an idea that keeps coming back for
more.